Results for 'Endicott Timothy Ao'

989 found
Order:
  1. Linguistic indeterminacy.Endicott Timothy Ao - 1996 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 16 (4).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  81
    Herbert Hart and the Semantic Sting: Timothy A.O. Endicott.Timothy Endicott - 1998 - Legal Theory 4 (3):283-300.
    Even to disagree, we need to understand each other. If I reject what you say without understanding you, we will only have the illusion of a disagreement. You will be asserting one thing and I will be denying another. Even to disagree, we need some agreement.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  3.  11
    Timothy Endicott.Timothy Endicott - 2017 - Problema. Anuario de Filosofía y Teoria Del Derecho 1 (11).
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  86
    Vagueness in law.Timothy Andrew Orville Endicott - 2000 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Vagueness in law can lead to indeterminacies in legal rights and obligations. This book responds to the challenges that those indeterminacies pose to theories of law and adjudication.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  5.  95
    Law and language.Timothy A. O. Endicott - 2002 - In Jules L. Coleman & Scott Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence & Philosophy of Law. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 935-968.
    The author argues that philosophers' attempts to use philosophy of language to solve problems of jurisprudence have often failed- the most dramatic failure being that of Jeremy Bentham. H.L.A.Hart made some related mistakes in his creative use of philosophy of language, yet his focus on language still yields some very significant insights for jurisprudence: the context principle (that the correct application of linguistic expressions typically depends on context in ways that are important for jurisprudence), the diversity principle (that grounds of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  6. Law is Necessarily Vague.Timothy Endicott - 2001 - Legal Theory 7 (1):377--83.
    In fact, law is necessarily very vague. So if vagueness is a problem for legal theory, it is a serious problem. The problem has to do with the ideal of the rule of law and with the very idea of law: if vague standards provide no guidance in some cases, how can the life of a community be ruled by law? The problem has long concerned philosophers of law; the papers at this symposium address it afresh by asking what legal (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  7.  57
    Legal misinterpretation.Timothy Endicott - 2022 - Jurisprudence 13 (1):99-106.
    In his book, _Interpretation without Truth_, Pierluigi Chiassoni articulates the sceptical view that the province of legal interpretation is ‘a province without truth’. A misinterpretation is a false interpretation, and I argue that the widespread phenomenon of legal misinterpretation gives us reason to resist the sceptical conclusion. The potential for a legal interpretation to be a false interpretation –a misinterpretation– implies that a legal interpretation can be true. And legal misinterpretations can be understood as interpretations (and not as the product (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. Herbert Hart and the Semantic Sting.Timothy Endicott - 2000 - In Jules L. Coleman (ed.), Hart's Postscript: Essays on the Postscript to `the Concept of Law'. New York: Oxford University Press UK.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  9. Putting interpretation in its place.Timothy A. O. Endicott - 1994 - Law and Philosophy 13 (4):451 - 479.
    What can a philosophical analysis of the concept of interpretation contribute to legal theory? In his recent book,Interpretation and Legal Theory, Andrei Marmor proposes a complex and ambitious analysis as groundwork for his positivist assault on “interpretive” theories of law and of language. I argue (i) that the crucial element in Marmor's analysis of interpretation is his treatment of Ludwig Wittgenstein's remarks on following rules, and (ii) that a less ambitious analysis of interpretation than Marmor's can take better advantage of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  10.  40
    Vagueness and Law.Timothy Endicott - 2011 - In Giuseppina Ronzitti (ed.), Vagueness: A Guide. Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag. pp. 171--191.
    The author argues that vagueness in law is typically extravagant, in the sense that it is possible for two competent users of the language, who understand the facts of each case, to take such different views that there is not even any overlap between the cases that each disputant would identify as borderline. Extravagant vagueness is a necessary feature of legal systems. Some philosophers of law and philosophers of language claim that bivalence is a property of statements in the domains (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11.  96
    The impossibility of the rule of law.Timothy A. O. Endicott - 1999 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 19 (1):1-18.
    No community fully achieves the ideal of the rule of law. Puzzles about the content of the ideal seem to make it necessarily unattainable (and, therefore, an incoherent ideal). Legal systems necessarily contain vague laws. They typically allow for change in the law, they typically provide for unreviewable official decisions, and they never regulate every aspect of the life of a community. It may seem that the ideal can never be achieved because of these features of legal practice. But I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12.  31
    Interpretation, jurisdiction, and the authority of law.Timothy Endicott - 2007 - American Philosophical Association Newsletter 6:14-19.
    People can be autonomous, if they are subject to authority. In particular, they can be autonomous if they are subject to the authority of law. I defend the first claim through a study of Joseph Raz's compelling account of authority; I claim that his work leads to the conclusion that autonomous judgment is needed to determine the jurisdiction of an authority, and to interpret its directives. I defend the second claim by arguing that law does not claim unlimited jurisdiction, and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  13.  26
    Human rights and the executive.Timothy Endicott - 2020 - Jurisprudence 11 (4):597-609.
    Where the law protects human rights, the executive branch of government does well if it complies with the law, and goes wrong if it does not comply. And then you may think that the paradigmatic fun...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14. Law and Language.Timothy A. O. Endicott - 2002 - In Jules Coleman & Scott J. Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law. New York: Oxford University Press UK.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  15. Are there any rules?Timothy Endicott - 2001 - The Journal of Ethics 5 (3):199-219.
    Widespread, deep controversy as to the content of the law of a community is compatible with the view that the law is a system of rules. I defend that view through a critique of Ronald Dworkin's discussion of Riggs v. Palmer 22 N.E. 188. Dworkin raised an important challenge for jurisprudence: to account for the fact that legal rights and duties are frequently controversial. I offer an explanation of the possibility of deep disagreement about the application of social rules, which (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16. Vagueness in Law.Timothy A. O. Endicott - 2000 - New York: Oxford University Press UK.
    Vagueness in law leads to indeterminacies in legal rights and obligations in many cases. The book defends that claim and explains its implications for legal theory. Vague language is the book's focus, but vagueness is not merely a linguistic feature of law. Law is necessarily vague. That fact seems to threaten the coherence of the ideal of the rule of law. The book defends a new, coherent articulation of that ideal.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17. The Logic of Freedom and Power.Timothy Endicott - 2010 - In Samantha Besson & John Tasioulas (eds.), The philosophy of international law. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 245-259.
    A state is sovereign if it has complete power within a political community, and complete independence. It may seem that the idea of sovereignty is objectionable because of two moral principles, or incoherent because of a paradox. The paradox is that a sovereign state must be capable of binding itself and must also be incapable of binding itself. The moral principles are that no state can justly exercise complete power internally, or complete independence (since complete independence would imply freedom from (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  53
    Adjudication and the Law.Timothy Endicott - 2005 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 27 (2):311-326.
    It can be compatible with justice and the rule of law for a court to impose new legal liabilities retrospectively on a defendant. But judges do not need to distinguish between imposing a new liability, and giving effect to a liability that the defendant had at the time of the events in dispute. The distinction is to be drawn by asking which of the court's reasons for decision the institutions of the legal system had already committed the courts to act (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19. The Value of Vagueness.Timothy Endicott - 2011 - In Andrei Marmor & Scott Soames (eds.), Philosophical foundations of language in the law. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  18
    What aspects of justice should not be the law’s concern?José Maria Sauca Cano & Timothy Endicott - 2020 - Jurisprudence 11 (3):416-416.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  60
    Vagueness and Legal Theory.Timothy A. O. Endicott - 1997 - Legal Theory 3 (1):37-63.
    The use of vague language in law has important implications for legal theory. Legal philosophers have occasionally grappled with those implications, but they have not come to grips with the characteristic phenomenon of vagueness: the sorites paradox. I discuss the paradox, and claim that it poses problems for some legal theorists (David Lyons, Hans Kelsen, and, especially, Ronald Dworkin). I propose that a good account of vagueness will have three consequences for legal theory: (i) Theories that deny that vagueness in (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22. Raz on Gaps: The Surprising Part.Timothy Endicott - 2003 - In Lukas H. Meyer, Stanley L. Paulson & Thomas Winfried Menko Pogge (eds.), Rights, culture, and the law: themes from the legal and political philosophy of Joseph Raz. New York: Oxford University Press.
    In English law, there are various ways in which contracts can be invalid or unenforceable because they are immoral — and yet English lawyers know that many contracts are conclusively binding. The first two sources of legal gaps that Joseph Raz identifies do not seem surprising. Vagueness in the sources of law leads to gaps in borderline cases, and there is a gap if the law includes inconsistent rules, with no way of deciding which is effective. In those situations it (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23. The Reason of the Law.Timothy Endicott - 2003 - American Journal of Jurisprudence 48 (1):83-106.
    Moral premises are required in sound reasoning to the conclusion that a community does or does not (more or less) attain the rule of law. Those moral premises include, for example, the principle that judges should act with comity toward executive agencies. A failure in that moral requirement of comity is a failure to attain the rule of law. Because the ideal of the rule of law necessarily has a moral content, there is a necessary connection between law and morality– (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. 'International meaning': Comity in fundamental rights adjudication.Timothy A. O. Endicott - 2002 - International Journal of Refugee Studies 13:280-292.
    In fundamental rights adjudication, should judges defer to the judgment of other decision makers? How can they defer, without betraying the respect that judges ought to accord those rights? How can they refuse to defer, without betraying the respect that judges ought to accord to other decision makers? I argue that only principles of comity justify deference, and their reach is limited. Comity never forbids the judges to take and to act upon a different view of fundamental rights from that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  44
    Authentic Interpretation.Timothy Endicott - 2020 - Ratio Juris 33 (1):6-23.
    I approach the identification of the principles of legal interpretation through a discussion of an important but largely forgotten strand in our legal heritage: the idea (and at some points in English law, the rule) that the interpretation of legislation is to be done by the law maker. The idea that authentic interpretation is interpretation by the law maker united the Roman Emperors Constantine and Justinian with Bracton, Aquinas, King James I of England, Hobbes, and Bentham. Already in the early (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  81
    How to Speak the Truth.Timothy A. O. Endicott - 2001 - American Journal of Jurisprudence 46 (1):229-248.
    Argues that some important problems in the theory of legal interpretation can be resolved with three techniques that John Finnis used in Natural Law and Natural Rights to address a methodological problem in jurisprudence: (1) The analogy principle: The application of a word such as “friendship” or “law” is not based on a set of features shared by each instance, but is based on similarities of a variety of kinds, seen by the people who use the words as justifying the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  57
    Morality and the Making of Law: Four Questions.Timothy Endicott - 2010 - Jurisprudence 1 (2):267-275.
    I address four questions that arise out of Nigel Simmonds's book, Law as a Moral Idea : Is politics a moral idea too? Is there any such thing as law making? Is there a right answer to every legal dispute? What justifies a judicial decision? To each question I propose an answer that shares much with Simmonds's views, but diverges. Simmonds is right to call law a 'moral idea', and that implies a connection between law and a moral ideal; in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. Proportionality and incommensurability.Timothy Endicott - 2014 - In Grant Huscroft, Bradley W. Miller & Grégoire C. N. Webber (eds.), Proportionality and the Rule of Law: Rights, Justification, Reasoning. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  20
    Philosophical Foundations of Precedent.Timothy Endicott, Hafsteinn Dan Kristjánsson & Sebastian Lewis (eds.) - 2023 - Oxford University Press.
    Philosophical Foundations of Precedent offers a broad, deep, and diverse range of philosophical investigations of the role of precedent in law, adjudication, and morality. The forty chapters present the work of a large and inclusive group of authors which comprises of well-established leaders in the discipline and new voices in legal philosophy. The magnitude of the resulting project is extraordinary, presenting a diverse array of innovative and creative philosophical investigations of the practice of adhering to past decisions, in law and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  18
    Properties of Law: Essays in Honour of Jim Harris.Timothy Endicott, Joshua Getzler & Edwin Peel (eds.) - 2006 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book comprises essays in law and legal theory celebrating the life and work of Jim Harris. The topics addressed reflect the wide range of Harris's work, and the depth of his influence on legal studies. They include the nature of law and legal reasoning, rival theories of property rights and their impact on practical questions before the courts; the nature of precedent in legal argument; and the evolving concept of human rights and its place in legal discourse.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  20
    What aspects of justice should not be the law’s concern?Timothy Endicott & José Maria Sauca Cano - 2020 - Jurisprudence 11 (3):416-416.
    We are delighted to present four articles that had their inception in a conference at Universidad Carlos III in Madrid in June 2016 on the question, ‘What aspects of justice should not be the law’s...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. The infant in the snow.Timothy Endicott - 2006 - In Timothy Endicott, Joshua Getzler & Edwin Peel (eds.), Properties of Law: Essays in Honour of Jim Harris. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Suppose that you are wandering across the tundra, and you find an infant, all alone, in the snow. She is incapable of discourse, and yet she has the same human rights as anyone who is capable of discourse. Those rights do not depend on the practices or conventions of your people, or hers. Human discourse and human conventions play no role in human rights. I elaborate these claims through a critique of J.W. Harris’s groundbreaking analytical account of human rights. I (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  21
    The Irony of Law.Timothy Endicott - 2013 - In John Keown & Robert P. George (eds.), Reason, morality, and law: the philosophy of John Finnis. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. pp. 327-345.
    John Finnis says that central cases of the concepts of social theory (such as the concept of law) fully instantiate certain characteristic values (which are instantiated in more-or-less watered-down ways in peripheral cases). Yet the instances of some such concepts (such as the concepts of slavery, of tyranny, and of murder) do not instantiate any value. I propose a solution to this puzzle: the central cases of such concepts focally instantiate certain ills. The central case of a concept essential to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  38
    What Human Rights Are There—if Any—and Why?Timothy Endicott - 2010 - Studies in Christian Ethics 23 (2):172-181.
    Are there human rights to a good such as social welfare, which depends on circumstances, and on the needs of a putative right-holder? Is justice constituted by rights? Does it take belief in God to understand the grounds of human rights? The essay responds to Nicholas Wolterstorff’s answers to these questions.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  26
    What use has approved.Timothy Endicott - 2020 - Ratio 33 (4):220-231.
    The meaning of a word is given by a customary rule for its use. I defend that claim and explain its implications by a comparison with customary rules in law. I address two problems about customary rules: first, how can the mere facts of social practice yield a norm? Secondly, how can we explain disagreement about the requirements of a custom, if those requirements are determined by the shared practice of the participants in a community? These problems can be resolved (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  18
    Preface.Endicott Timothy - 2001 - Legal Theory 7 (4):369-369.
    Preface to a Symposium on Vagueness and Law at Columbia University Law School on September 24 and 25, 1999. The purpose of the seminar was to provide an opportunity for philosophers of law, philosophers of language, and philosophers of logic to discuss problems about vagueness that are currently under debate in all three areas.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  8
    Timothy Endicott.Airey Immediate - 2012 - In Andrei Marmor (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Law. New York , NY: Routledge.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  23
    Interpretation without truth: a reply to critics.Pierluigi Chiassoni - 2022 - Jurisprudence 13 (1):139-152.
    Brian Bix, Damiano Canale, Timothy Endicott, Alessio Sardo, Frederick Schauer, and Giovanni Tuzet did me the honour of reading and critically commenting Interpretation without Truth (in the followi...
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. On the Instrumental Value of Vagueness in the Law.Hrafn Asgeirsson - 2015 - Ethics 125 (2):425-448.
    It is natural to think that law ought not to be vague. After all, law is supposed to guide conduct, and vague law seems poorly suited to do that. Contrary to this common impression, however, a number of authors have argued that vagueness in the law is sometimes a good thing, because it is a means to achieving certain valuable legislative ends. In this article, I argue that many authors—including Timothy Endicott and Jeremy Waldron—wrongly associate vagueness with instrumental (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  40.  23
    The Claim to Correctness, Rights, and the Ideal Dimension of Law: A Short Reply.Robert Alexy - 2020 - Ratio Juris 33 (3):283-290.
    These are the answers I gave to Brian Bix, Peter Koller, Ralf Posher, Torben Spaak, Timothy Endicott, and Jan Sieckmann at the end of a splendid conference day in 2018. The critique given to me concerned important aspects of three main themes in my work: the claim to correctness, human and constitutional rights, and the ideal dimension of law. In the last decades I have attempted to connect these themes systematically. The result is the idea of democratic constitutionalism (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. Modal Logic as Metaphysics.Timothy Williamson - 2013 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    Timothy Williamson gives an original and provocative treatment of deep metaphysical questions about existence, contingency, and change, using the latest resources of quantified modal logic. Contrary to the widespread assumption that logic and metaphysics are disjoint, he argues that modal logic provides a structural core for metaphysics.
  42. Rights, Culture, and the Law: Themes From the Legal and Political Philosophy of Joseph Raz.Lukas H. Meyer, Stanley L. Paulson & Thomas W. Pogge (eds.) - 2003 - New York: Oxford University Press UK.
    The volume brings together a collection of original papers on some of the main tenets of Joseph Raz's legal and political philosophy: Legal positivism and the nature of law, practical reason, authority, the value of equality, incommensurability, harm, group rights, and multiculturalism. James Griffin and Yael Tamir raise questions concerning Raz's notion of group rights and its application to claims of cultural and political autonomy, while Will Kymlicka and Bernhard Peters examine Raz's theory of multicultural society. Lukas Meyer investigates the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  15
    Legal Indeterminacy and Constitutional Interpretation.José Juan Moreso - 1998 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    In this book, I present the results of an investigation which began with an extended stay at Oxford's Balliol College during the first half of 1995. My visit to Oxford was made possible by a grant from the Spanish Ministerio de Educaci6n y Ciencia. My sincere thanks go to Joseph Raz who served as my supervisor in Oxford. For several points of the present study, conversations with Timothy Endicott in Oxford were also of great help. The book is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  44
    Vagueness, Comparative Value, and the "Lawmakers' Challenge".Hrafn Asgeirsson - 2012 - Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 98 (3):299-316.
    In "The Value of Vagueness," Timothy Endicott argues that vague law can be better than precise law. I think he is in many respects correct, but will suggest that we modify and supplement his framework in order to get a firmer grip on what I call the Lawmakers' Challenge: the scenario in which lawmakers find themselves when they must determine whether the consequences of precision are worse than the consequences of vagueness. This will allow us to identify several (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  52
    Suppose and Tell: The Semantics and Heuristics of Conditionals.Timothy Williamson - 2020 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    What does 'if' mean? Timothy Williamson presents a controversial new approach to understanding conditional thinking, which is central to human cognitive life. He argues that in using 'if' we rely on psychological heuristics, fast and frugal methods which can lead us to trust faulty data and prematurely reject simple theories.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  46.  52
    ``Knowing and Asserting".Timothy Williamson - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (4):489-523.
    Assertions are praised as true, informative, relevant, sincere, warranted, well-phrased, or polite. They are criticized as false, uninformative, irrelevant, insincere, unwarranted, ill-phrased, or rude. Sometimes they deserve such praise or criticism. If any respect in which performances of an act can deserve praise or criticism is a norm for that act, then the speech act of assertion has many norms. So has almost any act; jumps can deserve praise as long or brave, criticism as short or cowardly. But it is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   159 citations  
  47.  21
    The discourse of modernism.Timothy J. Reiss - 1982 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    On method, discursive logics, and epistemology -- Questions of medieval discursive practice -- From the middle ages to the (w)hole of Utopia -- Kepler, his Dream, and the analysis and pattern of thought -- Campanella and Bacon: concerning structures of mind -- The masculine birth of time -- Cyrano and the experimental discourse -- The myth of sun and moon -- The difficulty of writing -- Crusoe rights his story -- Gulliver's critique of Euclid -- Emergence, consolidation, and dominance of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  48. The Discourse of Modernism.Timothy J. Reiss - 1988 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 21 (1):69-72.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  49. Skeptical Theism, Abductive Atheology, and Theory Versioning.Timothy Perrine & Stephen J. Wykstra - 2014 - In Justin McBrayer Trent Dougherty (ed.), Skeptical Theism: New Essays. Oxford University Press.
    What we call “the evidential argument from evil” is not one argument but a family of them, originating (perhaps) in the 1979 formulation of William Rowe. Wykstra’s early versions of skeptical theism emerged in response to Rowe’s evidential arguments. But what sufficed as a response to Rowe may not suffice against later more sophisticated versions of the problem of evil—in particular, those along the lines pioneered by Paul Draper. Our chief aim here is to make an earlier version of skeptical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  50. Inexact knowledge.Timothy Williamson - 1992 - Mind 101 (402):217-242.
    Most of our knowledge is inexact, and known by us to be so. An example of such known inexactness will be described in some detail. The description seems to entail a contradiction. However, the paradoxical reasoning rests on an assumption. It will be suggested that the description is correct and this assumption false. Its failure will be explained by means of a picture of inexact knowledge in which the notion of a margin for error is central. This picture suggests diagnoses (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
1 — 50 / 989